nLab monoidal model category

Redirected from "symmetric monoidal model category".
Contents

Context

Model category theory

model category, model \infty -category

Definitions

Morphisms

Universal constructions

Refinements

Producing new model structures

Presentation of (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

Model structures

for \infty-groupoids

for ∞-groupoids

for equivariant \infty-groupoids

for rational \infty-groupoids

for rational equivariant \infty-groupoids

for nn-groupoids

for \infty-groups

for \infty-algebras

general \infty-algebras

specific \infty-algebras

for stable/spectrum objects

for (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

for stable (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

for (,1)(\infty,1)-operads

for (n,r)(n,r)-categories

for (,1)(\infty,1)-sheaves / \infty-stacks

Monoidal categories

monoidal categories

With braiding

With duals for objects

With duals for morphisms

With traces

Closed structure

Special sorts of products

Semisimplicity

Morphisms

Internal monoids

Examples

Theorems

In higher category theory

Contents

Idea

A monoidal model category is a model category which is also a closed monoidal category in a compatible way. In particular, its homotopy category inherits a closed monoidal structure, as does the (infinity,1)-category that it presents.

Definition

Definition

A (symmetric) monoidal model category is

equipped with the further structure of

such that the following two compatibility conditions are satisfied:

  1. (pushout-product axiom) For every pair of cofibrations f:XYf \colon X \to Y and f:XYf' \colon X' \to Y', their pushout-product, hence the induced morphism out of the cofibered coproduct over ways of forming the tensor product of these objects

    (XY)⨿XX(YX)YY, (X \otimes Y') \overset {X \otimes X'} {\amalg} (Y \otimes X') \longrightarrow Y \otimes Y' \,,

    is itself a cofibration, which, furthermore, is acyclic (i.e. also a weak equivalence) if ff or ff' is so.

    (Equivalently this says that the tensor product :C×CC\otimes \colon C \times C \to C is a left Quillen bifunctor.)

  2. (unit axiom) For every cofibrant object XX and every cofibrant resolution QIp II\emptyset \hookrightarrow Q I \stackrel{p_I}{\longrightarrow} I of the tensor unit II, the resulting morphism

    QIXp IXIXX Q I \otimes X \stackrel{p_I \otimes X}{\longrightarrow} I\otimes X \stackrel{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} X

    is a weak equivalence.

Remark

(internal hom Quillen adjunction)

Let XX be a cofibrant object, hence !X\varnothing \overset{\exists !}{\to} X a cofibration.

In this case the pushout-product axiom (Def. ) says that the tensor product functor X()X \otimes (-) preserves cofibrations and acyclic cofibrations. Since the ambient category is assumed to be closed monoidal category, so that this functor has a right adjoint internal hom [X,][X,-], this means that it is the left Quillen functor in a Quillen adjunction

𝒞 Qu[X,]X()𝒞 \mathcal{C} \underoverset {\underset{[X,-]}{\longrightarrow}} {\overset{X\otimes(-)}{\longleftarrow}} { \;\;\;\;\; \bot_{\mathrlap{Qu}} \;\;\;\;\; } \mathcal{C}

Remark

(meaning of the pushout product axiom)
The pushout-product axiom (above) is stronger than its implied statement in Exp. , while the latter might superficially seem to be all that would reasonably be required of a model-category theoretic version of a monoidal category.

It is at this point that the established tradition to just say “monoidal model category” for the above definition is somewhat misleading, in that Def. is really a model-category theoretic version of the stronger concept of closed monoidal categories (symmetric closed monoidal really, but the symmetry is not the subtle part). The arguably more accurate terminology “closed monoidal model category” for Def. is probably being avoided because Quillen (1967) originally introduced model categories in general under the name “closed model categories” with the adjective “closed” not meant to refer to its use in closed categories

Namely, the full strength of the pushout-product axiom is needed to imply that not only the tensor product \otimes but also its internal hom [,]:C op×CC[-,-] \,\colon\, C^{op} \times C \to C is homotopically well-behaved, to wit that [,][-,-] satisfies the pullback-power axiom, which in turn implies that not just [X,][X,-] but also [,A][-,A] are right Quillen functors for all cofibrant objects XX and fibrant objects AA.

In short, the pushout-product axiom is the model-category theoretic way to ensure that not just the tensor product, but also the internal hom as well as their joint relatin in a two-variable adjunction are homotopically meaningful.

Remark

(cofibrant tensor unit implies unit axiom)
As a special case of Rem. : If the tensor unit II happens to be cofibrant, then the unit axiom in def. is already implied by the pushout-product axiom.

(Because then QIIQ I \to I is a weak equivalence between cofibrant objects and such are preserved by functors that preserve acyclic cofibrations, by Ken Brown's lemma.)

Definition

(monoid axiom)

One says that a monoidal model category (Def. ) satisfies the monoid axiom if every morphism that is obtained as a transfinite composition of pushouts of tensor products XfX\otimes f of acyclic cofibrations ff with any object XX is a weak equivalence.

(Schwede-Shipley 00, def. 3.3.).

Remark

In particular, the axiom in def. says that for every object XX the functor X()X \otimes (-) sends acyclic cofibrations to weak equivalences.

Properties

Monoidal homotopy category

Abstractly

Proposition

For (𝒞,)(\mathcal{C},\otimes) a monoidal model category, def. , then the derived functor L\otimes^L of the tensor product makes the homotopy category of the model category itself into a monoidal category, such that the localization functor

γ:(𝒞,)(Ho(𝒞), L) \gamma \;\colon\; (\mathcal{C},\otimes) \longrightarrow (Ho(\mathcal{C}), \otimes^L)

is a lax monoidal functor.

Proof

Let VV be a monoidal model category, and consider it as a derivable category in the sense of (Shulman 11, section 8) with V QV_Q the subcategory of cofibrant objects and V R=VV_R=V. Then :V×VV\otimes :V\times V\to V is left derivable, i.e. it preserves the QQ-subcategories and weak equivalences. Since deriving is pseudofunctorial (and product-preserving) on the 2-category of derivable categories and left derivable functors, it follows immediately that Ho(V)Ho(V) is monoidal; this is (Shulman 11, example 8.13).

Now let V 0V_0 denote the category VV with its trivial derivable structure: only isomorphisms are weak equivalences, and all objects are both QQ and RR. Then of course Ho(V 0)=VHo(V_0) = V, and V 0V_0 is also a pseudomonoid in derivable categories. The identity functor Id:V 0VId : V_0 \to V is not left derivable, since it does not preserve QQ-objects; but it is right derivable, since we took all objects in VV to be RR-objects (ignoring the fibrant objects in the model structure on VV). Of course IdId is strong monoidal, and this monoidality constraint can be expressed as a square in the double category of (Shulman 11) whose vertical arrows are left derivable functors and whose horizontal arrows are right derivable functors; moreover the axioms on a monoidal functor may be expressed using products and double-categorical pasting in this double category. Therefore, it is all preserved by the double pseudofunctor HoHo; but Ho(Id)=γ:VHo(V)Ho(Id) = \gamma : V \to Ho(V). The only thing that is not visible to the double category is the invertibility of the monoidal constraint, and hence this is not preserved by the double pseudofunctor; thus γ\gamma is only lax monoidal.

Explicitly

Proposition

Let (𝒞,,1)(\mathcal{C}, \otimes, 1) be a monoidal model category with cofibrant tensor unit. Then the left derived functor L\otimes^L of the tensor product exists

𝒞 c×𝒞 c 𝒞 c γ×γ μ 1 γ Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞) L Ho(𝒞) \array{ \mathcal{C}_c\times \mathcal{C}_c &\overset{\otimes}{\longrightarrow}& \mathcal{C}_c \\ {}^{\mathllap{\gamma \times \gamma}}\downarrow &\swArrow_{\mu^{-1}}& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\gamma}} \\ Ho(\mathcal{C})\times Ho(\mathcal{C}) &\overset{\otimes^L}{\longrightarrow}& Ho(\mathcal{C}) }

and makes the homotopy category into a monoidal category (Ho(𝒞), L,γ(1))(Ho(\mathcal{C}), \otimes^L, \gamma(1)).

Moreover, the localization functor

γ:(𝒞 c,,1)(Ho(𝒞), L,γ(1)) \gamma \;\colon\; (\mathcal{C}_c, \otimes, 1) \longrightarrow (Ho(\mathcal{C}), \otimes^L , \gamma(1))

on the category of cofibrant objects is a strong monoidal functor with structure morphism the inverse of the above natural isomorpmism

μ X,Y:γ(X) Lγ(Y)γ(XY). \mu_{X,Y} \;\colon\; \gamma(X)\otimes^L \gamma(Y) \longrightarrow \gamma(X \otimes Y) \,.
Proof

For the left derived functor (def.) of the tensor product

𝒞×𝒞𝒞 \otimes \; \mathcal{C}\times \mathcal{C} \longrightarrow \mathcal{C}

to exist, it is sufficient that its restriction to the subcategory

(𝒞×𝒞) c𝒞 c×𝒞 c (\mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C})_c \simeq \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c

of cofibrant objects preserves acyclic cofibrations (Ken Brown's lemma, here).

Every morphism (f,g)(f,g) in the product category 𝒞 c×𝒞 c\mathcal{C}_{c}\times \mathcal{C}_{c} may be written as a composite of a pairing with an identity morphisms

(f,g):(c 1,d 1)(id c 1,g)(c 1,d 2)(f,id c 2)(c 2,d 2). (f,g) \;\colon\; (c_1, d_1) \overset{(id_{c_1},g)}{\longrightarrow} (c_1,d_2) \overset{(f,id_{c_2})}{\longrightarrow} (c_2,d_2) \,.

Now since the pushout product (with respect to tensor product) with the initial morphism (*c 1)(\ast \to c_1) is equivalently the tensor product

(*c 1) gid c 1g (\ast \to c_1) \Box_{\otimes} g \;\simeq\; id_{c_1} \otimes g

and

f (*c 2)fid c 2 f \Box_{\otimes} (\ast \to c_2) \;\simeq\; f \otimes id_{c_2}

the pushout-product axiom (def. ) implies that on the subcategory of cofibrant objects the functor \otimes preserves acyclic cofibrations. (This is why one speaks of a Quillen bifunctor, see also Hovey 99, prop. 4.3.1).

Hence L\otimes^L exists.

By the same decomposition and using the universal property of the localization of a category (def.) one finds that for 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} any two categories with weak equivalences (def.) then the localization of their product category is the product category of their localizations:

(𝒞×𝒟)[(W 𝒞W 𝒟) 1](𝒞[W 𝒞 1])×(𝒟[W 𝒟 1]). (\mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{D})[(W_{\mathcal{C}} \sqcup W_{\mathcal{D}})^{-1}] \simeq (\mathcal{C}[W^{-1}_{\mathcal{C}}]) \times (\mathcal{D}[W^{-1}_{\mathcal{D}}]) \,.

With this, the universal property as a localization (def.) of the homotopy category of a model category (thm.) induces associators: Let

𝒞 c×𝒞 c×𝒞 c (()())() 𝒞 γ 𝒞×𝒞×𝒞 η γ 𝒞 Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞) (() L()) L() Ho(𝒞),𝒞 c×𝒞 c×𝒞 c ()(()()) 𝒞 γ 𝒞×𝒞×𝒞 η γ 𝒞 Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞) () L(() L()) Ho(𝒞) \array{ \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c &\overset{((-)\otimes(-))\otimes (-)}{\longrightarrow}& \mathcal{C} \\ {}^{\mathllap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C}}}}\downarrow &\swArrow_{\eta}& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C}}}} \\ Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) &\overset{((-)\otimes^L(-))\otimes^L (-)}{\longrightarrow}& Ho(\mathcal{C}) } \;\;\;\,,\;\;\;\;\; \array{ \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c &\overset{ (-) \otimes ( (-) \otimes (-) ) }{\longrightarrow}& \mathcal{C} \\ {}^{\mathllap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C}}}}\downarrow &\swArrow_{\eta'}& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C}}}} \\ Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) &\overset{ (-) \otimes^L ( (-) \otimes^L (-) ) }{\longrightarrow}& Ho(\mathcal{C}) }

be the natural isomorphism exhibiting the derived functors of the two possible tensor products of three objects, as shown at the top. By pasting the second with the associator natural isomorphism of 𝒞\mathcal{C} we obtain another such factorization for the first, as shown on the left below,

()𝒞 c×𝒞 c×𝒞 c (()())() 𝒞 = α = 𝒞 c×𝒞 c×𝒞 c ()(()()) 𝒞 γ 𝒞×𝒞×𝒞 η γ 𝒞 Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞) () L(() L()) Ho(𝒞)𝒞 c×𝒞 c×𝒞 c (()())() 𝒞 γ 𝒞×𝒞×𝒞 η γ 𝒞 Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞) (() L()) L() Ho(𝒞) = α L = Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞)×Ho(𝒞) () L(() L()) Ho(𝒞) (\star) \;\;\;\;\;\; \array{ \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c &\overset{((-)\otimes(-))\otimes (-)}{\longrightarrow}& \mathcal{C} \\ {}^{\mathllap{=}}\downarrow &\swArrow_{\alpha}& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{=}} \\ \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c &\overset{ (-) \otimes ( (-) \otimes (-) ) }{\longrightarrow}& \mathcal{C} \\ {}^{\mathllap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C}}}}\downarrow &\swArrow_\eta& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C}}}} \\ Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) &\overset{ (-) \otimes^L ( (-) \otimes^L (-) ) }{\longrightarrow}& Ho(\mathcal{C}) } \;\;\;\;\;\; \simeq \;\;\;\;\;\; \array{ \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c \times \mathcal{C}_c &\overset{((-)\otimes(-))\otimes (-)}{\longrightarrow}& \mathcal{C} \\ {}^{\mathllap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C}}}}\downarrow &\swArrow_{\eta'}& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\gamma_{\mathcal{C}}}} \\ Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) \times Ho(\mathcal{C}) &\overset{((-)\otimes^L(-))\otimes^L (-)}{\longrightarrow}& Ho(\mathcal{C}) \\ {}^{\mathllap{=}}\downarrow &\swArrow_{\alpha^L}& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{=}} \\ Ho(\mathcal{C})\times Ho(\mathcal{C})\times Ho(\mathcal{C}) &\underset{(-)\otimes^L((-)\otimes^L (-))}{\longrightarrow}& Ho(\mathcal{C}) }

and hence by the universal property of the factorization through the derived functor, there exists a unique natural isomorphism α L\alpha^L such as to make this composite of natural isomorphisms equal to the one shown on the right. Hence the pentagon identity satisfied by α\alpha implies a pentagon identity for α L\alpha^L, and so α L\alpha^L is an associator for L\otimes^L.

The above equation on pasting composites of natural isomorphism is equivalently just the coherence law for a monoidal functor:

(γ(X) Lγ(Y)) Lγ(Z) α γ(X),γ(Y),γ(Z) L γ(X) L(γ(Y) Lγ(Z)) η η γ((XY)Z) γ(α) γ(X(YZ)). \array{ (\gamma(X) \otimes^L \gamma(Y)) \otimes^L \gamma(Z) &\overset{\alpha^L_{\gamma(X), \gamma(Y), \gamma(Z)}}{\longrightarrow}& \gamma(X) \otimes^L (\gamma(Y) \otimes^L \gamma(Z)) \\ {}^{\mathllap{\eta'}}\uparrow && \uparrow^{\mathrlap{\eta}} \\ \gamma( (X \otimes Y) \otimes Z ) &\underset{\gamma(\alpha)}{\longrightarrow}& \gamma(X \otimes (Y \otimes Z)) } \,.

Examples

Classical homotopy theory

Simplicial presheaves

If the underlying site has finite products, then both the injective and the projective, the global and the local model structure on simplicial presheaves becomes a cartesian monoidal model category with respect to the standard closed monoidal structure on presheaves.

See at model structure on simplicial presheaves the section Closed monoidal structure.

Monoidal presheaves

More generally, if a small category 𝒮\mathcal{S} has finite products and \mathcal{M} is a cofibrantly generated symmetric monoidal model category, then the functor category Func(𝒮 op,)Func\big(\mathcal{S}^{op}, \mathcal{M}\big) with its object-wise monoidal category-structure and with the projective model structure on functors is itself a monoidal model category (see Yalin 2012, Lem. 3.8; White 2017, Cor. 5.20; Pavlov & Scholbach 2018, inside proof of Prop. 7.9).

Homological algebra and stable homotopy theory

With respect to a symmetric monoidal smash product of spectra:

(Schwede-Shipley 00, MMSS 00, theorem 12.1 (iii) with prop. 12.3)

The standard example of a monoidal model category whose unit is not cofibrant is the category of EKMM S-modules.

Categorical model structures

Model structure on GG-objects

Assumption

Let \mathcal{E} be a category equipped with the structure of

such that

Proposition

Under these conditions there is for each discrete group GG the structure of a monoidal model category on the Borel model structure BG\mathcal{E}^{\mathbf{B}G} of objects in \mathcal{E} equipped with a GG-action, for which the forgetful functor

BG \mathcal{E}^{\mathbf{B}G} \to \mathcal{E}

preserves and reflects fibrations and weak equivalences.

See Berger & Moerdijk (2006) 2.5.

Model structure on monoids

See model structure on monoids in a monoidal model category.

References

Textbook accounts:

Historically, the first mention of monoidal model categories (without the unit axiom) under this name is in

The term “pushout smash product” is used for the case of smash products in pointed categories (such as of pointed simplicial sets or symmetric spectra):

The general notion of monoidal model categories and their pushout-product axiom appears in:

Although the earliest mentions of terminology appear to be these sources indicated above, the notion itself is older. In particular, Hovey (1999), p. 107 credits the definition of a Quillen bifunctor to Dwyer, Hirschhorn, Kan Smith (2004) (which had for years earlier been “in preparation”), and the definition is of course just a small variant of the definition enriched model categories, which in its specialization to simplicial model categories is due to

(The corresponding pullback-power axiom is axiom “SM7” in Quillen (1967).)

The unit axiom together with the fact that the homotopy category is monoidal in this case is due to Hovey.

Conditions for the existence of induced monoidal model structure on Reedy model categories:

Some relevant homotopy category background:

The monoidal structures for a symmetric monoidal smash product of spectra are due to

Further variation of the axiomatics is discussed in

The monoidal model structure on the Borel model structure BG\mathcal{E}^{\mathbf{B}G} is discussed for instance in

Relation to symmetric monoidal (infinity,1)-categories (in particular, that every locally presentable symmetric monoidal (,1)(\infty,1)-category arises from a symmetric monoidal model category) is discussed in

Monoidal Reedy model structures are discussed in

On enhancement of monoidal model categories up to strong monoidal Quillen equivalence:

and for monoidal simplicial model categories:

See also:

Last revised on August 10, 2024 at 20:51:32. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.